These selections provide a brief but comprehensive introduction to Fichte’s philosophical system and his place in the history of German Idealism. In addition to some of Fichte’s most influential texts, such as the First and Second Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and The Basis of Our Belief in a Divine Governance of the World, Breazeale has translated, for the first time into English, several other writings from the same period, including Attempt at a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre, Other short essays, including Fichte’s replies to the charge of atheism, extend the discussions of the Introductions and respond to criticisms. Breazeale’s substantial Introduction supplies the context needed for a sound appreciation of Fichte’s enterprise and achievement.
Johann Gottlieb Fichte was a German philosopher. He was one of the founding figures of the philosophical movement known as German idealism, a movement that developed from the theoretical and ethical writings of Immanuel Kant. Fichte is often perceived as a figure whose philosophy forms a bridge between the ideas of Kant and the German Idealist Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel. Recently, philosophers and scholars have begun to appreciate Fichte as an important philosopher in his own right due to his original insights into the nature of self-consciousness or self-awareness. Like Descartes and Kant before him, the problem of subjectivity and consciousness motivated much of his philosophical rumination. Fichte also wrote political philosophy, and is thought of by some as the father of German nationalism. His son, Immanuel Hermann Fichte, was also a renowned philosopher.
Fichte has been the German Idealist I have read the most of. I can't deny thinking that some of the ideas he was working with were interesting. I don't know if this collection of introductions to his idealist system are more clearly and comprehensively elucidating, but they do offer further explanations of the system that may allow one to see it from a greater vantage point. His letters, I am finding, provide an even greater context to his Wissenchaftslehre (loosely translated as the science of knowledge). They do make more evident the theological implications of his system. I would definitely advise people studying Fichte to consult his correspondences as well. This volume also contains his notorious essay on divine governance where he claimed that there was no God beyond the moral ordering of the world. Obviously, that statement was ridiculous and got him into trouble. Some going so far as to even claim Fichte was an atheist. He wasn't an atheist, but some of his statements, including that one, indicate some amount of erroneous thinking and more than a tinge of arrogance. Some of his responses to the charge of atheism are included here. They do not help to vindicate the statement however. His main defense was that people failed to understand what he was thinking. Often Fichte resorts to the defense that people cannot critique his system until they understand his system. This usually amounts to anyone who criticizes it, fails to understand it; in other words, understanding it means to believe it, thus it is beyond criticism until one agrees with it! Part of his defense to the atheist charge is bound up with his system and boils down to the way he uses terminology; order cannot be static, it must be dynamic; and dynamism denotes life and thus God in actuality, or some such line of thinking. Even aside from the misusing of standard terminology in idiosyncratic ways in a public setting, my main issue is that the statement in question still makes God dependent on mundane notions; at least that is the way it appears from wording. The wording is poor and really indefensible as it stands. No amount of rhetorical gymnastics saves the statement. It is one example of a number of statements that show that Fichte imbued his system with a Godlike perfection. He was not the last idealist to do that. Hegel was certainly guilty of doing the same. In Hegel's case, certain members of the New Hegelians (e.g. Marx) were able to interpret his system atheistically. It stands to reason that much of the erroneous hubristic system building found in Fichte was also found in Hegel. Both found themselves in close proximity to charges of atheism (in the latter case positively, and in the former negatively) because of the kinds of claims they were making; at least through implication, if in no other manner. I like Fichte to a degree. Some of his notions are indeed profound, so I think he is worth reading. I feel the same way about Hegel; although I have had a tendency to favor Fichte. I don't have all of the antipathy towards Idealism that was often found in Kierkegaard, although I approach Idealism with some amount of ambivalence. I recognize that there are problems with Idealism; but in certain respects, and in very particular contexts, some of the ideas found in this tradition are accurate -if not used as some all-encompassing box wherein we fit all of existence, that is. Many of Kierkegaard's criticisms are my own, but I find more things of value here than Kierkegaard did, or at least would've admitted to.
A well translated collection of writings pertaining to the wissenschaftslehre. Helpful in introducing the reader to fichte's system. I only wish that the editor included a preface to each work individually in order to contextualise it within fichte's complex philosophical development.
I won't claim to say that I understood everything in this admittedly dense text which deserves a much closer reading. However, my reaction to the first and the second introductions were wholly different - the first introduction read like an insubstantial rant against people who don't understand Fichte with an unjustified (and convenient) exclusion of his opponents as folks who are just not "meant for" it because their personality is not oriented towards freedom. In contrast, the Second Introduction and Chapter One are quite interesting and could have been a fantastic book if Fichte had fully carried it out.
The "I" which must always be posited, as per Fichte, cannot be mistaken with the ego or personality:
The relationship between reason and individuality presented in the Wissenschaftslehre is just the reverse: Here, the only thing that exists in itself is reason, and individuality is something merely accidental. Reason is the end and personality is the means; the latter is merely a particular expression of reason, one that must increasingly be absorbed into the universal form of the same. For the Wissenschaftslehre, reason alone is eternal, whereas individuality must ceaselessly die off. Anyone who will not first accommodate his will to this order of things will never obtain a true understanding of the Wissenschaftslehre.
Instead, Fichte's "I" is simply the existence of a subject which reflects upon itself, and no name/form may be necessarily associated with this subjective self.
Though you may have included many things in your concept of the I which I have not (e.g., the concept of your own individuality, for·this too is signified by the word "I"), you may henceforth put all of this aside. The only "I" that I am concerned with here is the one that comes into being through the sheer self-reverting act of your own thinking.
To me, in Chapter One, Fichte's positing of an infinite subject and object being present in the act of self-consciousness at first suggests that rational knowledge (involving a mental positing of the "I") will always retain duality - this is why the mind cannot reach the true Self. One must go beyond the rational processes of the mind involved in thought to reach a nondual Self:
what was the gist of the line of reasoning we just pursued, and what is the real reason why the nature of consciousness could not be grasped in this way? The gist of the argument was as follows: I can be conscious of any object only on the condition that I am also conscious of myself, that is, of the conscious subject. This proposition is incontrovertible. It was, however, further claimed that, within my self-consciousness, I am an object for myself and that what held true in the previous case also holds true of the subject that is conscious of this object: this subject too becomes an object, and thus a new subject is required, and so on ad infinitum. In every consciousness, therefore, the subject and the object were separated from each other and each was treated as distinct. This is why it proved impossible for us to comprehend consciousness in the above manner.
But then I don't understand how his saying, on the next page, that our self-consciousness is the only place where subjectivity and objectivity is united, is possible. Doesn't the argument of the previous paragraph (that we become conscious of ourselves as an object only and hence retain duality still apply?) - they may be inseparably united, but it doesn't follow that the subject-object distinction is entirely dissolved - it may still continue in ordinary existence.
He says that the self-positing act does not produce a noumenal I and considers this "the greatest of absurdities" - while this suggests a possible argument against nondual Indian thought, even in those disciplines Brahman is describes as pure consciousness, so they may still stand.
This is where many of the hitherto assumptions of philosophy break down - that we can be rationally convinced of truth (Fichte famously exclaims here that our philosophy depends on the kind of person we are), but we also get a more subjective emphasis on intuitions that may not be rationally thought of, but still remain necessary for our existence.
Really good introduction to Fichte's philosophy. And was a surprisingly easy and sassy read compared to a Kant. You can really feel Fichte's frustration with people not understanding him.
So I'd say read this before the new 1794 Wissenschaftslehre, then read the collection of early philosophical writings. All translated by the same translater of this book.